首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   12029篇
  免费   138篇
各国政治   346篇
工人农民   1169篇
世界政治   411篇
外交国际关系   415篇
法律   7319篇
中国政治   36篇
政治理论   2458篇
综合类   13篇
  2021年   28篇
  2020年   51篇
  2019年   52篇
  2018年   1335篇
  2017年   1291篇
  2016年   1098篇
  2015年   128篇
  2014年   95篇
  2013年   308篇
  2012年   270篇
  2011年   1020篇
  2010年   1083篇
  2009年   664篇
  2008年   844篇
  2007年   772篇
  2006年   109篇
  2005年   149篇
  2004年   268篇
  2003年   237篇
  2002年   116篇
  2001年   189篇
  2000年   140篇
  1999年   106篇
  1998年   50篇
  1997年   57篇
  1996年   54篇
  1995年   79篇
  1994年   70篇
  1993年   57篇
  1992年   82篇
  1991年   88篇
  1990年   78篇
  1989年   65篇
  1988年   86篇
  1987年   81篇
  1986年   98篇
  1985年   111篇
  1984年   95篇
  1983年   88篇
  1982年   43篇
  1981年   37篇
  1979年   40篇
  1978年   39篇
  1977年   34篇
  1975年   31篇
  1974年   46篇
  1972年   27篇
  1971年   31篇
  1970年   30篇
  1968年   32篇
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
251.
In this piece, I argue that promises need not be kept just because they were made. This is not to say, however, that unwise, unhappy, and unfortunate promises do not generate obligations. When broken promises will result either in wrongful gains to promisors or wrongful losses to promisees, obligations of corrective justice will demand that such promises be kept if their breach cannot be fully repaired. Thus, when a broken promise will constitute a deliberate loss transfer for personal gain, the duty not to exact unjust enrichment (a wrongful gain) will require a promisor either to honor her promise or craft a means of ensuring that the promisee’s impoverishment is not traded for her enrichment. And when a broken promise will constitute the culpable imposition of a reliance-based injury on a nonculpable promisee (a wrongful loss), the duty to make others whole when one has purposefully, knowingly, or recklessly injured them will require one either to keep one’s promise or to fashion a remedy for its breach that ensures that the promisee is left no worse off than he would be had the promise not been made. This account explicitly parts ways with normative powers theories of promising. It places no weight at all on the raw fact that a promise has been made. Instead, it locates the gravamen of a promissory violation in the harm that is caused to a promisee who nonculpably relies upon and changes her position in anticipation of the prediction about the promisor’s future conduct that is embedded in his promise. Absent any adverse reliance on the part of a promisee, there is nothing that gives rise to an obligation of performance or repair on the part of the promisor. But this account is also to be distinguished from utilitarian theories that take promises to be instruments of wealth maximization that properly give way whenever the reason for honoring them speaks in favor of violating them. On my account, the balance of reasons for action that determines the morality of performance includes deontological rights and duties, agent-relative permissions, and Hohfeldian liberties. As I shall argue, even if one rightly concludes that one has no duty either to keep a promise or to craft a remedy for its breach, one must nevertheless remember that virtue requires one to be or become the kind of person who often goes beyond the call of duty. But the fact that virtue often requires us to do what we have no duty to do should not cause us to confuse its conditions with the conditions of right and wrong action. We have a duty to keep promises or to otherwise protect the reliance interests that they generate only when failing to do so will lead either to our own unjust enrichment or to others’ unjust injury. And this means that we have a duty to keep promises in far fewer circumstances than is commonly believed.  相似文献   
252.
We discuss the mechanisms related to quadratic voting, from Vickrey’s counter-speculation mechanism and his second-price auction, through the family of Groves mechanisms and its most notable member, the Clarke mechanism, to the expected externality mechanism, Goeree and Zhang’s mechanism, the Groves–Ledyard mechanism, and the Hylland–Zeckhauser mechanism. We show that each mechanism that involves collective decisions has a quadratic aspect and that all of the mechanisms that we discuss are applications of the fundamental insight that for a process to be efficient, all parties involved must bear the marginal social costs of their actions.  相似文献   
253.
254.
255.
256.
257.
258.
259.
260.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号